Home Page

Critical Thinking Guidelines

 

The Chinese' have a proverb which says that there are three sides to every question: my side, your side, and the right side.
Critical thinking overview

Have a question or comment?

Intellectual Standards
Critical Reading
The Right Questions
Propaganda
To sum up

 

An educator is one who, in the phrase of Robert Hutchins, "seeks to teach people how to think for themselves." An educator wants people to seek the truth. To this end he will present them with facts; he will appeal to their reason; he will follow an argument to whatever conclusions may be warranted by the evidence.
 
   

Descartes  Why is that some men's opinion are certainly more sensible than others, but that some of us conduct our thoughts along different paths, and do not fix our attention on the same objects. 

His answer here is: to be possessed of a vigorous mind is not enough; the important thing is rightly to apply our mind to what we are doing.

 Descartes then goes on to say that " the greatest minds, though they are capable of the high excellences" are likewise subject to the greatest errors, and "those who travel very slowly may yet make far greater progress, provided they keep always to the straight road, than those who, while they run, forsake it." For himself, he adds (despite his magnificent achievements in found­ing analytical geometry), he "never fancied his mind to be in any respect more perfect than that of the average man." On the con­trary, he had often wished that he was "equal to some others in promptitude of thought, or in clearness and distinctness of imagi­nation, or in fullness and readiness of memory." And these, he thought, are the only qualities that contribute to the perfection of the mind. But good sense, or reason, is the same in all of us.

 To what, then, did Descartes owe his great success as a thinker? He tells us: "It has been my singular good fortune to have very early in life found a methodical way of thinking. In this way I have gradually augmented my knowledge, and raised it little by little to the highest point which the mediocrity of my talents and the brief duration of my life will permit me to reach." The method he found so useful, he tells us, involves four simple pre­cepts:

1. Never to accept anything as true which you do not clearly know to be such; that is, to avoid hasty judgments and prejudice.

2. To divide each difficulty under examination into as many parts as possible, or into as many as necessary for the solution of the problem.

3. To begin with the things that are simplest and easiest to un­derstand, and then to ascend to knowledge of the more complex.

4. To make enumerations so complete, and reviews so compre­hensive, that you may be assured that nothing is omitted.

 

Let us briefly sum up what Descartes is telling us in the re­marks we have quoted from his Discourse on Method. By and large, he says, all men '"' have reason (good sense) in equal degree. And so, though a man may admit that another is cleverer than he, or more learned, or possessed of wider knowledge, he will not admit that the other has more capacity -for distinguishing truth from error (when the facts are clearly known). And, by and large, he is right in this. There are of course enormous differ­ences between one human being and another in quickness of ap­prehension, power of imagination, and in the fullness and readi­ness of memory. But the chief difference between one person's understanding and another's is due to the fact that some people use the proper methods of thinking, whereas others do not.

Now, whatever we may think of the usefulness of Descartes' own simple precepts for attacking a problem (and the full signifi­cance of these precepts in his philosophy is by no means simple), his general conclusions do point to an encouraging thesis: We are all capable of understanding, and we may improve our under­standing by using the right methods of thinking. The right methods will help us to solve our problems more efficiently. Our problems may be "scientific" ones, in the narrow sense of that term, but they may also arise in business and social relations, in salesmanship (or anti-salesmanship, that is, sales-resistance when we play the role of consumer) and in politics or love.

But the reader may have been thinking of some further objec­tions to Descartes' assumptions. One may question his assumption that all men are rational. That is not the story we get from mod­em psychology, the reader may say, and certainly it does not jibe with our own experiences with our fellow men. We all know people who do not seem to be reasoning creatures, and, if they are satisfied with their good sense, why, so much the worse for them. And, the reader may go on: Don't most people seem to be controlled by their emotions? Are people really interested in the truth? Don't people always believe only what they want to believe?

From "The Art of Making Sense ... A Guide to Logical Thinking by Lionel Ruby

   
   

Applying Intellectual Standards to an Author's Reasoning

Clarity: Is the author clear (or is further explanation needed)?

Accuracy: Are the statements (or claims) of the author true or should they be questioned?

Relevance: Does the author support his/her views with relevant reasons and evidence?

Depth: Do the author's answers address the complexities in the questions at issue? Does the author's reasoning lead to significant and far reaching implications?

Logic: Does the author's reasoning make sense? Do the conclusions follow from the information given?

Breadth: Does the author approach the issues from multiple viewpoints (where relevant) or is his/her reasoning too narrow minded? Are opposing viewpoint considered or presented?

 

Critical Reading

What key questions or problems does the author

raise?

What is the author's purpose?

 What information, data, and evidence does the author present?

What key concepts guide the author's reasoning?

What key conclusions is the author coming to? Are those conclusions justified?

What are the author's primary assumptions?

What is the author's viewpoint?

What are the

implications of the author's reasoning?

Foundation for Critical Thinking www.criticalthinking.org

back

   

The Right Questions  ... The answer is in the Questions..

To give you an initial sense of the skills that Asking the Right Questions will help you acquire, we will list the critical questions for you here.  

1. What are the issues and the conclusion?

 

2. What are the reasons? are beliefs, evidence, metaphors, analogies, and other statements offered to support or justify conclusions.

 

3. What words or phrases are ambiguous?  ... check the key terms in the issues...

 

4. What are the value conflicts and assumptions?  ... values are standards of conduct

 

5. What are the descriptive assumptions?  ...assumptions are ideas that, if true, enable us to claim that particular reasons provide support for  a conclusion.

 

6. What is the evidence?

 

7. Are the samples representative and the measurements valid?

 

8. Are there rival hypotheses?

 

9. Are there flaws in the statistical reasoning?

 

10. How relevant are the analogies?

 

11. Are there any errors in reasoning?

 

12. What significant information is omitted?

 

13. What conclusions are consistent with the strong reasons?

 

14. What are your own value preferences in this controversy?

back

Propaganda;

Similar considerations apply to the other techniques of the propaganda analysts. A "glittering generality" is a statement like "Woman's place is in the home," or "What is good for business is good for the country." There is a wisecrack which says that generalizations are always false, and statements like the ones just quoted undoubtedly ought to be qualified. But certainly propa­gandists have no monopoly on the use of such generalizations. And a testimonial may be good or bad, depending upon its source, on the competence of the testifier, and on his probable lack of prejudice. Testimonials are not necessarily dishonest.

The analysis of these "propaganda techniques" calls our atten­tion to the possibility that we may be permitting emotion to sway us, and we are reminded that we ought to look into the evidence. But language alone does not distinguish propaganda from other forms of discourse. Propagandists may avoid these techniques altogether, and non-propagandists may use them.

What is meant by propaganda in this discussion? Its nature may be made clearer by contrasting the propagandist and the educator. There are some, of course, who deny the distinction and who tell us that "the advocacy of what we believe in is edu­cation; the advocacy of what we don't believe in is propaganda." But this is not what most of us mean by these words. An educator is one who, in the phrase of Robert Hutchins, "seeks to teach people how to think for themselves." An educator wants people to seek the truth. To this end he will present them with facts; he will appeal to their reason; he will follow an argument to whatever conclusions may be warranted by the evidence. An educator will, or ought to, have his own point of view, his own preferences, and he will recommend his personal beliefs to his audience, but he will state the grounds on which he holds these beliefs, and he will state the major objections to them. Thus his students will be able to judge for themselves concerning the validity of his arguments and the truth or falsity of his beliefs.

We have been speaking of an ideal educator, a truth-seeker. But a propagandist, in the strict sense, is not interested in the truth for its own sake, or in spreading it. His purpose is differ­ent. He wants a certain kind of action from us. He doesn't want people to think for themselves. He seeks to mold their minds so that they will think as he wants them to think, and act as he wants them to act. He prefers that they should not think for them­selves. If the knowledge of certain facts will cast doubts in the minds of his hearers, he will conceal these facts.

It may be said that there are no educators in this ideal sense, and that, really, everyone is a propagandist. "The propaganda with which we agree is called education; the propaganda with which we disagree is called propaganda." If we accept this no­tion, we are forced to deny the distinction between tricksters and truth-seekers. This confusion of categories may be fostered by those who are afraid of the truth and who therefore want us to disbelieve whatever we read about them. If they can get us to believe that "everything is propaganda," we will believe noth­ing, including the truth about them. But to accept the wholesale skepticism suggested by the phrase "everything is propaganda" is just as foolish an attitude as to be completely un-skeptical. There are two errors we ought to avoid: to be too trusting and to be too skeptical. Some people believe everything they read in the papers, and others believe nothing. We must learn to be discriminating— to distinguish between what it is reasonable to believe, what it is reasonable to doubt, and what we ought to dismiss as probably false.

back

   

To sum up.

 We have noted that there are three kinds of lan­guage, or purposes in speaking, and we examined the distinction between neutral and emotive words. We saw how emotion is employed in order to get action. Propaganda, we saw, has a directive purpose, for the propagandist wants us to act. The question, "What shall we do in order to protect ourselves against propaganda?" is misleading. The question assumes that propaganda is bad, and we cannot say that this is so without making certain distinctions. Insofar as propaganda seeks to get us to act by emotional appeals coupled with a concealment of facts—facts that might make us think about the merits of the proposal'-it is "bad" as a method. It is possible of course that the propagandist may have our best interests at heart, so that his goal may be a good one. An illustration of "good" propaganda is found in some of the War Bond posters used during the last war. These posters showed a Marine lying on a foreign beachhead. Underneath the picture was an exhortation to buy Bonds so that our armed forces would not lack ammunition. The real purpose of buying bonds was to avoid the inflationary effects of excess purchasing power. This propaganda had a desirable goal, for inflation would have impeded the war effort. And perhaps the truth would not have been so effective, for "Avoid inflation!" has little emotional ap­peal. We can only hope that propaganda of this sort will some day be unnecessary, even in good causes. This will happen when the people can be trusted to know, and act upon the truth.

Another reason why it is misleading to speak of "protection against propaganda^ is that this implies that there is a special kind of defense against propaganda. There is no magic amulet whereby one may exorcise its evils. The only defense against propaganda which seeks to hurt us is to add to our knowledge and to sharpen our critical abilities. We shall then know how to protect ourselves against the various forms of hokum.

The Chinese' have a proverb which says that there are three sides to every question: my side, your side, and the right side.

back

   
   
  Prepared by  Bill Wolfson.  
Last Updated
sept., 2007